Ali's Blog
kitty Gif

Home home GIF About about GIF Entries post GIF Chat chat GIF Kool Webpages cool GIF Guestbook Guestbook GIF Kool Books reading GIF Truth Table math GIF Contact Phone GIF

The Human Rights Discourse during the Qatar World Cup

So, i was all set to indulge in a glorious world cup opening ceremony, complete with a seitan double burger and fries (don't @ me) but, of course, the universe had other plans. Instead of the usual pomp and circumstance, i was greeted with a bunch of talking heads yapping about Qatar's human rights record. I get it, human rights are important and all that jazz... but can't we just have one day of mindless football fandom without being guilt-tripped into caring about the plight of migrant workers? I mean, i'm a Qatari, and i've been waiting for this moment for TEN YEARS but no, the BBC had to go and boycott the ceremony in the name of "human rights advocacy". Thanks for ruining the party, bbc. I'm left feeling all conflicted; part of me wants to just enjoy the beautiful game, but another part of me is all like "but wait they have a point, what about the human rights?!". Can't we just have a simple, uncomplicated world cup experience? is that too much to ask?

My initial thought was: I am extremely pro-human rights! Finally, the world was shining a light on the somewhat darker corners of my little-known country. I suppose anyone who strives for social justice in their own country would find such a feat encouraging.

 

It slowly became apparent that the criticism is clearly not being made in good-faith. But so what? Does that matter if it's bringing about ends which I seek? Apparently yes, because it isn’t. Bad faith as palpable as that which was on display is terrible, if only from a rhetorical point. The presenters’ feigning outrage, use of generalising rhetoric, invocation of rehearsed buzzwords, and utterances of the phrase ‘human rights abuse’ as some kind of magical incantation—all left me with a bad aftertaste. Don't get me wrong - I agreed with many of their points (from the Kefala system to male guardianship laws and the persecution of sexual minorities). But the self-indulging nature of the delivery struck me as an attempt at mere moral grandstanding that is tinged by Orientalism.

 

Turns out, my Spidey senses were spot on. Once the World Cup ended, the human rights chatter went silent faster than a referee's whistle.  It was as if the whole thing was just a convenient excuse for people to virtue-signal against those primitive Arabs. As I originally wrote in another essay, much of human rights rhetoric seems to come from a position of rationalist condescension, and hardly ever seeks to manipulate the sentiments and sympathies of unconvinced populations (in practical terms, this convincing would have been, for example, interviewing migrant workers, Qatari women and sexual minorities about their narrative so that their fellows can more easily sympathise). It is not enough that we simply howl out expressions such as ‘X is a human right!’.

 

Unfortunately, it was British broadcasters preaching to a mostly British choir; a monologue about a projected other, instead of a genuine dialogue. Though the audience (and me with it) were already bought into the human rights presuppositions and were pre-convinced of the conclusions which Gary Lineker & co.’s were sermonising, I knew that this form of rationalist moral posturing will not persuade anyone else, especially the people who most need convincing.

Was it a Clash of Civilisations?

It did far worse than not persuade them. The larger rhetoric around human rights seemed to have triggered an effectively anti-human rights reaction from many Qataris, if only out of spite. A moral panic among Qataris ensued about the infiltration of sexual minorities into Qatar, as if none already existed. Suddenly, rainbows were public enemy number one, feared as if they were some sort of demonic gateway for an invasion of gay zombies. And charges of orientalism, western exceptionalism, cultural imperialism and hypocrisy (the stock and trade of what is now called “post-colonial studies”) were the main rhetorical weapons of deflection in Qatar’s toolkit.

Twitter avatar for @Qatari

And then, low and behold, I saw it again. Samuel Huntington's "Clash of Civilizations" theory was suddenly trending again, and not in a good way. His ghost must have been chuckling in his grave, seeing his belligerent theory come to life about the so-called clash of monolithic entities, ‘Islam vs the West’. Superficially, it seemed to have been instantiated and Huntington's prediction vindicated. Scenes of Qatari imams on evangelising rampages, Muslims in Rohingya lifting portraits of MBS and cheering for Saudi Arabia’s national team, tournament officials confiscating rainbow flags, Palestine armbands being turned into anti-LGBT symbols, a talk of sports teams as colonisers and colonised, the German national team gesturing protests about LGBT persecution.

 

As I watched the madness unfold, I couldn't help but think of these totalising, grand stories that began circulating in the 90’s about such soppused civilisational clashes, uncommunicating communities, moral and cultural incommensurablites and so on. “The great divisions among human kind and the dominating source of conflict,” wrote Huntington, “will be cultural”. “The clash of civilizations will dominate global politics. The fault lines between civilizations will be the battle lines of the future.”

Twitter avatar for @tariqpanja

Twitter avatar for @BrasilEdition

Twitter avatar for @Justin_D_Martin

Whether or not we're starring in some cosmic civilisational showdown (I'm leaning towards "not"), there's no denying our world is a patchwork quilt of different culturally-rooted perspectives. I'm lucky enough to have a front-row seat to this global potluck, watching as people from all walks of life scratch their heads in confusion over each other's thoughts and behaviours, mainly as a result of a failure to set the conditions for a fruitful social negotiation about our global village (and the global events that are held within it). In this particular case, journalists and commentators to government officials and football audiences, all were largely convergent on their confusion about what ‘human rights’ are and how to go pragmatically negotiate them.

 

My main concern here is untangling the intellectual knots we've tied ourselves into, the arguments and rejoinders utilised by both camps and how they are often mischaracterised. The conviction which underpins the essay is that we must first seek a higher level of critical self-understanding of the philosophical presuppositions we hold as human rights advocates in order to engage with other populations in good faith. I am specifically concerned with making explicit the normative and metanormative understanding of human rights in the hopes of unclouding mutual communication, at the very least on an intellectual level.

Cultural Boundaries are Chimeras

Meaningful communication cannot thrive in the stuffy confines of the traditionalists' cultural isolationism on the one hand, and UNESCO's "windowless" cultural relativism on the other hand (as cheekily dubbed by anthropologist Clifford Geertz, where human communities are in his words “semantic monads”). But let's face it—boundaries are about as real as unicorns when it comes to cultures. Cultures are always swapping ideas, food, fashion, and more in a never-ending, primordial game of cultural musical chairs. One may go so far as saying, with Geertz, that other cultures are constitutive of one another, that routes supervene on roots. Static “natives”, anchored in place and untouched by outside contact have probably never existed outside the misguided writings of meandering 20th century European anthropologists.

 

The real roadblocks to cross-cultural communication aren't impenetrable walls (ala Huntington) but our own cultural inattention, dogma and stubbornness. Sure, differences exist, but they're not “incommensurable”, as some cultural theorist would have it. They constantly shift and blend into one another. And so in that sense, in the words of philosopher Paul Feyerabend, “potentially, every culture is all cultures.” That is to stay that, at the boundaries of cultures, you always find ambiguities, contradictions and pluralities; you find people juggling their cultural identities, whether it's me balancing my Qatari socialisation with my Western education - moving in and out of different cultural prototypes, mixing and matching - or gay and feminist Muslims navigating their faith, gender and sexuality. People tolerate such ambiguity, and they settle apparent contradictions by simply dissolving them. So if we accept that boundaries are what they are as chimeras, we can start treating any culture's practices as our own practice. Torture, for example, is an offence regardless of the culture in which it occurs and not some mysterious "other cultural" practice. And we'll always find local voices condemning it, and those voices is where any sort of intervention should begin.

Twitter avatar for @Qatari


The Great Human Rights See-Saw: Universalism vs. Relativism

In the human rights game, we find two teams on the playing field. Bear in mind, we're painting with broad strokes here, but such simplification is sometimes needed for analysis. Team West features a motley crew of Western journalists, human rights activists, liberals of all flavours, and mostly individuals from WEIRD (Western, Educated, Industrious, Rich and Democratic) populations who got over their bipartisanism to condemn the other team. They're often found shouting from their moral high ground, hurling phrases like "X is a violation of human rights!" as if they're tossing confetti at a parade.

 

Team Qatar includes ‘subaltern’ petro-rich Qataris, PR-savvy social media firms, genuinely aggrieved non-WEIRD audiences, postcolonial professors, and FIFA. This team retorts by (understandably) throwing around accusations of cultural imperialism, Western exceptionalism, and hypocrisy. Some go on to then weaponise outdated liberal values like "non-judgment" to legitimate illiberal practices and hush up dissenters. When it suits them, they'll also cosy up to normative cultural relativism, which is a prescription for tolerating the moral practices of other cultures no matter how much they themselves might disagree with them.

 

This was exemplified by the FIFA president’s pre-tournament address to the press when he claimed that the ‘West’ is being hypocritical when criticising Qatar for the conditions it puts migrant workers and exclaims that "for what we Europeans have been doing for 3,000 years around the world, we should be apologising for the next 3,000 years before starting to give moral lessons to people".

Twitter avatar for @binnahar85

Twitter avatar for @GrantWahl

The retort made by the Qatar team, when assessed charitably, is intended to be a sort of internal critique against the ‘West’ team, as no one in the ‘Qatar’ team is sincerely a normative relativist. It was made possible because ‘the West’ team was framed as holding two untenable positions, though never explicitly defined. And when you don’t explicitly define your position, people will define it—and mischaracterise it if that furthers their goals—for you. These positions are as follows.

Right above Culture (normative universalism):

Some human rights advocates subscribe to normative universalism and a universal procedural justice system, which posits that  certain moral principles, like human rights, should apply universally— they are relevant and binding to all humans regardless of cultural or individual differences. In wanting to make operationalise prescriptions universally, such as ‘All humans have a right not to be tortured’, they attempt to “ground” this first-order normative prescription by way of a metaphysical (second-order) thesis, that is, by affirming metaethical realism.  This is the view that there are moral facts, like human rights, that are not made true by anyone’s stances. There are these ‘natural’ moral obligations which we might call ‘rights’ that come about simply in virtue of being a featherless biped, and these moral obligations are made true independent of anything anyone thinks about them—they are not made the case by our perspectives.

 

Some arrive at the same metaethical realist view by way of arguing for the existence of normative ‘reasons’. All individuals are universally conferred with minimum moral obligations that cannot be trampled by the interests of their culture or group. The justification for these moral obligations is that they are backed up by stance-independent 'normative reasons'. So, to say that there are human rights against torturing babies for fun is to say that you have a normative reason to not torture babies for fun. The idea is that there are reasons for action independent of our desires, attitudes, beliefs, choices etc., as in the case where you have a reason to not spend your life counting spades of grass, whether you like doing so or not. (See my critique of this view here).

Right to Culture (normative relativism):

On the other hand, human rights advocates of whom Claud Levi-Strauss had approvingly called ‘UNESCO cosmopolitanists’ affirm what I will call the naive normative cultural relativist view. This view is a prescriptive position popularly held among early 20th century anthropologists which holds that we must tolerate the moral practices of different cultures (this may be known as the twin principles of non-interference and non-judgment). This is exemplified in UNESCO’s Our Creative Diversity 1995 report which reiterates the tweet shared earlier, in saying that cultures deserve to be treated “with respect” (as if there’s clearly bounded ‘cultures’ that are not further divisible into contradictory subcultures), and frames the issue not as ‘human rights vs culture’ but as ‘a human right to culture’, but then equivocates on the word ‘culture’ between ‘a way of life’ and ‘an aesthetic work’. This ‘respect our culture’ rhetoric is exactly the type of rhetoric which the Saudi government in its treatment of women, nationalists in their demand for stricter border controls, the genital mutilators in Somalia, the Islamic State and ethnocentrists all over the world can all happily rejoice with.

Taken together, the human rights advocates express the following propositions:

  1. We hold that human rights norms are universally applicable, and they are ‘grounded’ by stance-independent moral reasons.
  2. We ought not judge the moral norms of other cultures.

Can’t Have Your Cake and Eat it Too

Seting aside the metaethical point (i.e., the ‘grounding’ part), clearly there is a contradiction here; human rights advocates are endorsing normative universalism and normative relativism simultaneously. That is, there are claiming that we ought to tolerate other individuals or groups that act against human rights because such an act is a cultural act simplicter, and that we ought not tolerate individuals or groups that act against human rights irrespective of culture. Human rights advocates are thus framed as moral schizophrenics and condemned as hypocrites for making two contradicting normative claims. They can’t have their cake and eat it too; they can either affirm normative universalism or normative relativism, buy not both at once.

 

I suggest that human rights advocates jettison normative cultural relativism as there is no good reason to uphold a position which precludes a capacity of moral indignation and contempt—or interference if the situation so needs. It is antithetical to a ‘human rights’ project.

 

Human rights, by their nature, involve universal prescriptive norms that are insensitive to the cultural standards of the actant individual or group. If Siberian Shamans had historically developed a ritual to kill odd-ordered born babies for fun, then presumably, the human rights project aims to in some sense interfere with that ritual. After all, the Universal Declaration explicitly confers rights to individuals (the odd-order babies), not groups (the Shamans). And all human rights start off with some universal normative judgment, such as ‘no distinction shall be made on the basis of ...etc.’

 

Or consider a real historical example: the practices of the early Ache tribe of Paraguay as described in 1972 by anthropologist Pierre Clastres in his Chronicle of the Guayaki Indians. The tribe was reported by Pierre to practice cannibalism, kill elderly people with Alzheimer because they are thought to have harboured dangerous vengeful spirits, have pre-pubertal sex, abandon their aged, beat menarcheal girls with tapir penises and cut them with broken glass, and what’s more, they held ‘clubfights’ where men would fight sometimes to the death, similar to Roman gladiator contests. It would be rather odd to say that the human rights project was intended to protect the ‘right to culture’ of the Ache tribal men rather than protecting the menarcheal girls’ ‘right above culture’, viz. their right from an abusive cultural practice. The retort by the men that such a practice is a “cultural” practice to which they have the right to will fly in the face of the girls’ rights above such culture.

Human Rights Advocates Should Not “Ground” Normative Universalism

As discussed earlier, human rights advocate often wish to “ground” the normative universalism which the human rights culture is based on with metaethical realism, that is, by saying that they are backed up by stance-independent moral facts that apply to everyone, at all times, everywhere and independent of any perspectives or cultures. I suggest human rights advocates give up on metaethical moral realism for they would otherwise be opening themselves up to accusations of smuggling in their own social practices into something ineluctable and transcendental that is intrinsic to all humans and then calling it ‘true independent of any stances’. I suggest that human rights advocates abandon the attempt to “ground” universalism altogether and instead endorse a pragmatist approach to human rights without ever eluding to the metaphysical nature of such rights.

A better reformulation of the human rights advocates’ position would thus be the total inversion of the characterisation above, i.e., by affirming metaethical cultural relativism (with a deflationary account of truth) across the board accompanied by a normative universalism (while allowing a plurality of culturally-specific values; such as, for example, the right to own a goat or the right to die among family, etc.):

We hold that the cluster of moral norms we call ‘human rights’ are true and ought to be prescribed universally. We also affirm that we ought to not tolerate cultures and individuals that act in opposition to those norms.

We do not wish to ‘ground’ the truth of the human rights norms, nor the subsequent normative claims on universal prescription and non-tolerance. Any attempt to do so will be circular.

Instead, we acknowledge that human rights norms (and the subsequent normative claims) are true or false relative to standards. When indexed to our standards as human rights advocates, they are true. When indexed to the standards of Medieval Christians, they are mostly false. Yet, we are none the worse for that.

The fear often expressed when endorsing such metaethical relativism is a common rhetorical sleight of hand which equivocates metaethical considerations (‘the truth of human rights is relative to standards’) with normative considerations (‘we ought not judge cultures with different standards’). But metaethical relativism does not logically entail any normative consequences (the clue is in the name). Acknowledging human rights as stance-dependent norms that are indexed to our standards doesn’t mean that we are precluded from normatively judging practices that contravene them.

To use an analogy, we acknowledge food or music taste as being relative to preferences but that doesn’t impede our ability of having strong food or music preferences or in judging, or even going to war against, people with contravening preferences if we are so inclined. Remember, the comparison between human rights and food/music is their meta-normative characteristics, and specifically NOT how important they are or what ought be done about them or how much they should be imposed on others—those are all normative, not metanormative, stances. It just so happens that a feature of music/food preferences is that they are not typically imposed on others and people do not usually ‘judge’ others for holding different music and taste preference. But, in principle, someone can be a meta-normative anti-realist about music/taste/aesthetics etc. and simultaneously hold a normative stance that their preferences ought be imposed on everyone. This is the view I advocate for with respect to human rights. We can be anti-realist about human rights and simultaneously hold a normative stance that human rights are extremely important and prefer that everyone else follows those norms.

Unfortunately, many human rights activists think that in order to be rhetorically effective they must adopt, even if implicitly, moral realism as a metaethical stance, in which moral sentences are ‘made true’ by the intrinsic nature of the world and not by our evaluative standards.1 They think that they must insist that rules for action really matter only if those rules were independent from us, in which case they will only ‘psuedomatter’, and that this will win them more rhetorical points among unconvinced populations. They think that maintaining a metaethical relativism or constructivism will make those rules arbitrary and deprive them from their necessary ‘oomph’.

Philosopher Richard Rorty highlights this psychological dilemma within liberals who use rationalist rhetoric of the Enlightenment to justify their liberal convictions:

These liberals hold on to the Enlightenment notion that there is something called a common human nature, a metaphysical substrate in which things called “rights” are embedded, and that this substrate takes moral precedence over all merely “cultural” superstructures. Preserving this idea produces self-referential paradox as soon as liberals begin to ask themselves whether their belief in such a substrate is itself a cultural bias. Liberals who are both connoisseurs of diversity and Enlightenment rationalists cannot get out of this bind. Their rationalism com­mits them to making sense of the distinction between rational judgment and cultural bias. Their liberalism forces them to call any doubts about human equality a result of such irrational bias. Yet their connoisseurship forces them to realize that most of the globe’s inhabitants simply do not believe in human equality, that such a belief is a Western eccentricity. Since they think it would be shockingly ethnocentric to say “So what? We Western liberals do believe in it, and so much the better for us,” they are stuck.

Rorty’s advice follows the line of thought I’m getting at, which is to say ‘yes, our cultural practices are not universally held nor are they etched into the fabrics of the cosmos, but so what?’ There is no principled distinction between cultural bias and rational judgment if we acknowledge that we cannot reach out from under our cultural practices and institutions into a God’s eye view. We cannot, in other words, shed our frame of reference temporarily and rise up into a neutral, omniscient point of view and then start to compare all frames of references. The terms we fall back on are, after all, always self-consciously ethnocentric: ‘as a… Qatari’.., ‘Marxist’, ‘Liberal’, ‘Muslim’, ‘anthropologist’ I think thus and so. And so Rorty urges human rights advocates “to take with full seriousness the fact that the ideals of procedural justice and human equality are parochial, recent, eccentric cultural developments, and then to recognize that this does not mean they are any the less worth fighting for . . . [and] the best hope of the species”. In this construal of what Rorty calls ‘liberal ironism’, Rorty is echoing the liberalism philosopher Isaiah Berlin when he ended his famous essay Two Concepts of Liberty by saying that his ideal political community is one that realises ‘the relative validity of [its] convictions and yet stand for them unflinchingly’.

1

In technical jargon, that there are antecedently existing ‘truth-makers’ tracked by some truth-tracking faculty. Usually the truth-makers are how human beings are qua humans i.e., qua some alleged intrinsic ‘human nature’ that’s truth-tracked by ‘human reason’.